Public masturbation: a seminal issue!

As Heretic TOC’s castration theme proved rather controversial, today’s topic will be soporifically bland, in order to calm everyone down. Rummaging around for something suitably anodyne, I needed to look no further than a reader’s comment commending public masturbation. I am sure we all agree with this reader that only “rules imposed by the humourless and convivially challenged” could stand in way of allowing anyone of an exhibitionist bent to jerk off in the shopping mall for the entertainment of passersby. Why, without a few sad killjoys standing in the way it might even catch on as a popular busking performance – a new source of income, perhaps, for superannuated porn actors.
Even so, it might come as a bit of a surprise that only a week or so ago it was reported that a court in Sweden had declared it is legal to masturbate in public. A 65-year-old man had been charged with assault after dropping his shorts on a beach in Stockholm and masturbating in front of people. But the court decided there was no assault, a verdict the public prosecutor said he accepted because nobody had been “targeted”. He said: “For this to be a criminal offence it’s required that the sexual molestation was directed towards one or more people. I think the court’s judgement is reasonable.” He added: “…we can conclude that it is okay to masturbate on the beach.” A targeted act might be considered disorderly conduct but, otherwise, carry on jerking your junk!
The exceptional nature of this judgement reminds us that “civilization” has largely been built upon the dourly restrictive precepts of the “convivially challenged”. The very dawn of European civilization, in Ancient Greece, affords us a tantalising glimpse of how alternative, let-it-all-hang out (literally) values might have developed and where they might have taken us in some parallel universe. They are to be found in the life of the philosopher Diogenes of Sinope, who achieved notoriety for many aspects of his lifestyle, including public wanking. He also defecated in the theatre – making him surely the most pungently effective theatre critic ever. Believing in a simple life, shorn of the hypocrisy and artificiality of much human conduct, he lived as a beggar on the city streets, with only a tub for shelter. Opposing Plato, he insisted that reason should replace authority in guiding human affairs – a point of special note for a particular contributor here who questions the standing of those whose reasoning he doesn’t like!
Being asked where in Greece he saw good men, Diogenes replied, “‘Good men nowhere, but good boys at Sparta.” Make of that what you will! He believed virtue was better revealed in action than in theory. He used his simple lifestyle and behaviour to criticise the social values and institutions of what he saw as a corrupt society in Athens and elsewhere. He publicly mocked Alexander the Great – who admired the oddball philosopher’s pluck and confessed that if he were not Alexander he would gladly have been Diogenes. Standing against property and government, the sage can be seen as an early anarchist – as can Lao-tze (Laozi), from a similar depth of antiquity in Ancient China, whose name was cited with approval by a reader who also expressed his dislike of “moral philosophy” – a point that perhaps has some resonance for us when we note one of Lao-tze’s sayings: “When goodness is lost, it is replaced by morality.”
We can see instantly what the legendary founder of Dauism means, or at least have our own ideas about it. The word “morals” derives from “mores” which means customs and rules of supposedly proper behaviour. All too often it means conventions which have needlessly constricted our lives like a corset, and which have no sound basis in fostering goodness. It is this conception of morals that gives “moral philosophy” a bad name: it is seen by some as mere moralising. In his excellent BL novel The Moralist, Rod Downey offers a vision of morality as window-dressing: we rationalise our own behaviours as moral while denouncing (especially if we are comfortably conventional in our tastes, and thus part of the moralising majority, as we might say) the desires and lifestyles of others.
Reviewing The Moralist, I welcomed Downey’s exploration of a deeply cynical take on life. His novel advances a way of thinking which guards against sentimentality and the smug moral complacency of authoritarians. Downey, although he does not shit and wank in public, so far as I am aware, might even be seen as a modern Diogenes in one respect: Diogenes was not only cynical, he was a founding father of the Cynics, one of the most famous and influential of all schools of philosophy. Unlike modern cynicism, though, which is often seen as a corrosively negative view of life, the cynicism advanced by Diogenes and his school was not lacking in a positive, constructive side – to an alarming degree, some might feel. A key idea was living in harmony with nature, which carried with it all the hair-shirt implications we now see in the modern environmental movement: green enthusiasts tend to berate us for being slaves to luxury and wasteful consumption. Diogenes would have agreed, and he also inspired the early Christian ascetics.
In other words, although Diogenes rejected moral conventions in such spectacular fashion, he very much believed in living a good life, and that we need to cultivate mental clarity in respect of what constitutes such a life. In effect he was saying, forget morals (“mores”, mere customs) and think about ethics, which considers moral values and their application in a systematic way. Confusingly, though, this is often known as moral philosophy!
Let us, then, call it ethics, for clarity. Indeed, this word, clarity, is absolutely key to the reason why moral philosophy – oops, sorry, ethics – was raised in the blog comments in relation to what mentally impaired young people are allowed to do or not do in the sex lives.
I said I would deal today with public masturbation, but in fact the Good Ship Heretic TOC has been stealthily navigating towards the more general issue of how to resolve ethical dilemmas. These dilemmas are occasions when we are faced with a puzzling conflict between different things, each of which seem desirable: such as upholding the seemingly legitimate rights of both parties when two people are at odds. We could just let the parties slug it out by force on a “might is right” basis, but in most cases – such as when one of the parties is mentally handicapped – we tend to feel a principled approach is needed in order to untangle the web of competing interests and resolve the issue as fairly as possible.
This sort of procedure is generally taken for granted in serious discussion, but it has been contested here on the grounds that “…humanity drives law, not abstraction. The merits of any given matter supported by factual evidence and interpreted fairly and reasonably on a case by case basis are primary, not some moral treatise…”
Judges, to be sure, must judge on a case by case basis. That is what they are paid to do. But our critic of “moral philosophy” had already specified in an earlier post that cases should be settled not just by a judge interpreting the law but that the law itself must be “reasonable and fair. It must observe the person’s human rights. It must comply with policy on social justice.” But the concept of “human rights” did not just plonk itself down among us. It did not spring, fully formed, like Athena from the head of Zeus, nor arrive with preternatural sagacity, like Lao-tze, who is said to have stayed in the womb for decades before being born with a full grey beard and adult wisdom. While even little children of less wondrous beginnings than Lao-tze have a sharp intuitive sense of fairness, the development of rights that prevent slavery, give votes to women and allow gays to marry, has been the work of ethical deliberations – and, yes, “moral treatises” – that validate and encourage political pressure towards such ends. These ethical ideas, centuries in the making, are a work in progress, and we must hope that further work will advance the cause of sexual rights for children and the minor attracted.
In the meantime, we should at least do our best to understand the work that has already been done and its significance to us. This very much includes the rights of the mentally handicapped, which have proved such a contentious issue here. This theme – of mental handicap – is one I hope to pursue shortly, both for its own interest and because a principled investigation, grounded in the ethical reasoning that underpins human rights, has implications for considerations of “consent” that can be applied more widely.

0 0 votes
Article Rating
Subscribe
Notify of
guest

16 Comments
Newest
Oldest Most Voted
Inline Feedbacks
View all comments
consignee

Difficult to have a sense of humour regarding public masturbation when your next door neighbour engages in this practice opposite your front door during school hours. He is profoundly disturbed and brain damaged by his own admission, an alcoholic substance abuser well known to Police and will no doubt plead diminished responsibility if this goes to court. Gentlemen, if this happens to your mother, sister, wife or daughter you may not be so frivolous and philosophical about the rights of the individual. I have informed all my neighbours about this incident for the protection of their families in fear that he will escalate this perverse behaviour.
I’m reminded that one sign of the ‘end of days’ in Revelations will be that good is considered bad and bad will be good. God help us all!

willistina556

Gil,   On the beach, or at the barricades.   You’ll soon know sub-tWit Tina, wearing nowt but ye traditonale riot gear, tin hat, tanga, flippers, and a BIG grin.   With laughing kidz milling all around.        

Mr Phil

It doesn’t detract from any of the points you made, but several commentators, including the one you linked to, note that Sweden has a ‘disorderly conduct’ law, which can be used to prosecute public masturbation. What appears to have happened in this case is that the prosecutor tried to ram home the more serious charge of sexual assault, on the grounds that two girls saw the act (and reported it). The court rejected this, saying the act was not ‘directed’ at the girls, and he wasn’t convicted of disorderly conduct because he wasn’t charged with it. But he could have been. One Swede, commenting on a Guardian report, said that the prosecutor’s statement had been garbled in translation, not least by omission of the word ‘not’: it should have read: “this does not mean it is OK to masturbate on a public beach.” The anglophone press like to have their preconceived ‘angle’ — here, crazy Swedish liberalism — and bend the story to fit. But perhaps what we really have is a story of crazy Swedish authoritarian feminism attempting a landgrab, and not totally unsuccessfully, for the judge implied that if the masturbation had been judged to be directed at the girls, it would have counted as sexual assault.

Mr Phil

Well, I don’t know that my version is true either. Let’s just say the story doesn’t quite add up. But I’m glad the anglophone press version was there to launch you into such a thoughtful, not to say finely erudite column.
I like your references to Diogenes and Laozi, which chime with my own idea that the authority for ethics is not some abstract system, but humanity’s evolved capacity, implicit in the ideas of Diogenes (and other ancient Greek virtue ethicists) and Laozi, and since reified and named by the Christians as conscience. Systems like Kant’s and Bentham’s are merely attempts to simulate its workings, each of them emphasising one of the considerations that conscience tries to weigh up (for Kant, individual dignity; for Bentham, collective happiness), but even if a universal system were possible (and it is not: on many questions the two systems starkly disagree; and there are more where they came from), it would still not fulfill the function of a real, organic conscience, which is to weigh up imponderables and decide what is right in real, ambiguous situations, on the instant. Which is a long-winded way of agreeing with Laozi and Diogenes.
It’s the Enlightenment principle of Freedom of Conscience writ large (and not limited, as it has usually been, to a choice between organised religions). This implies rejecting any moral role for the state, because there are no universal moral values to impose. The state’s role rather should be one of peace keeping, in as neutral and minimal a way as possible. As you suggest, a somewhat anarchistic ideal, which one can at best muddle towards, but it could be useful at least to have some handle on the ideas behind it.

peterhoo

Mr. Phil, your added comments on the case Tom refers to, plus your ideas of how a society could balance these two items of ethics and morality, is very interesting.
You might be interested, and may already know, inside Catholic teaching the follower is instructed to follow their conscience, no priest, bishop, or Pope for that matter, can over rule what the believer’s conscience guides them to do! (Although I would be misleading a reader if I did not make the point the Catholic leaders ask church members to consider what the clergy say, pray about what it is that they are deciding, and integrate it all inside what they choose to do.) To follow one’s faith for a Catholic is actually supposed to be a sophisticated process, sadly it is often portrayed as blind, unthinking, and often misguided.

Gil Hardwick

Translation notwithstanding, as any policeman anywhere will tell you it’s not so much a matter of ‘don’t do it’ but ‘don’t get caught’.
I’m damned if I know how on earth it’s possible to stop people doing it, and find myself thinking more (as would most reasonable and thoughtful) about that sad lonely man out there on some windswept beach by himself, with no friends.
So, happy with friend Edmund’s concordance, and dear Tina’s Willy on the posi-convivial sector, which is at the end of the day what all of this is about.
No surprise that many more will refer increasingly as time goes by to “that lovely man”; “those lovely people”, than “those paedos”.
I wonder if we’ll ever meet up? It won’t be a formal biannual general meeting with all the rules and heavy formality and ailing grouchy old men à la IPCE, it will be a riot.

willistina556

Cut to the VERY short-strokes, in far less than 200 letters.   “Do Unto Others, Do No Harm, Honi Soit Qui Mal Y Pense”.   Pre-Web public-bog wall legends: “Bobbed-hair, BIG eyes, Snub nose, Rosebud lips, Short-skirt/shorts, White sox…Oh God I’ve Cum Again!” “After 4pm, Fun Sex Mister?”

Edmund

When I read Gil’s remark about those objecting to public wanking being “convivially challenged”, a delightfully incisive expression I fear I shall plagiarise with disgraceful frequency, Diogenes immediately sprung to my mind too, so I’m delighted you have raised his spectre in a typically witty piece. For a more complete understanding of Diogenes’s philosophy, you might also though have mentioned the reason he gave for wanking: that “he wished it were as easy to relieve hunger by rubbing an empty stomach” (Diogenes Laertius, Lives of the Eminent Philosophers VI 46).
However, I would suggest that a more important omission is the other side of the coin. As you say he “achieved notoriety;” much of what he did provoked outrage, but he got away with doing it all the same. I doubt he could have done so if his detractors had been stifled from mocking him; his freedom of self-expression went hand in hand with theirs. This is what I would say made ancient Greece so culturally vibrant and intellectually productive compared to our intellectually strait-jacketed society. Instead of being treasured, heresy has now become so strongly disapproved of that any adoption of new values has soon to be followed by the stifling of contrary views. Consider how fast Europe has moved from imprisoning gays to imprisoning anyway who expresses disgust for them as one of many examples. In the most unlikely event that the majority in the future were to stop finding public wanking convivially challenging and it was accordingly allowed, it would be only a short time before the same killjoy majority insisted on the imprisonment of anyone who mocked it like Diogenes’s compatriots. What is missing for hopes of truly enlightening debate is indeed conviviality.
Edmund, author of Alexander’s Choice, an Eton boy’s love story, http://www.amazon.com/Alexanders-Choice/dp/1481222112

Gil Hardwick

First, I don’t know anybody here commending public masturbation, only that some have a sense of humour about it. The admonition is merely if they’re not hurting anybody, mind your own business.
In the case cited, all we are told is the man was masturbating. How so? Was it erect, being rubbed to ejaculatory spasm, making an exhibition, or being on a beach did he merely have his bathers down cleaning sand off it?
There is no judge who will fail to take into account such degrees of offending, and in that the particular judge is correct in arguing that no matter who may feel offended, until proven beyond reasonable doubt the man was not actually offending. Two criteria must be met, again beyond reasonable doubt, the guilty act itself (actus reus) and the guilty mind behind the act (men rea).
Suffice I expect that being dragged before the court is itself sufficient chastisement.
Here too, the wise man is not condoning public masturbation, merely determining that the person was not guilty of any offense. I have myself been involved in such cases, where the judge has agreed with defense that the court is not there to judge morality but legality, and the guy likewise acquitted.
Second, on Diogenese and the cynical tradition (Gr, ??????? = dog = behaving like a dog), nudity, masturbating, body functions, are primarily subversive; quintessentially subversive, though in this sense the political statement can be pointed and deliberate, fulfilling the guilty mind (mens rea) requirement most likely leading to conviction.
That situation is quite different from a child, or someone acting like a child. In that too, dogs are funny; as our Australian National Treasure Michael Leunig has it, “naked opportunists, moral vacuums, uneducated pleasure-driven philistines.”
That’s the reason we keep them as pets. In age care centres they keep pet dogs to tangibly assist in promoting the health and morale of the elderly. For this reason too they make good pets for children, always my favourite.
Third, on Daoist perspectives, see also the most influential of all Western teachers, one Jesus of Nazareth, called Christ, who admonished the crowd, “Judge not, lest ye be judged!” He further taught, “Suffer the children to come unto me, for theirs is the Kingdom of Heaven.”
Finally, on Downey’s ‘The Moralist’, view Bertolucci’s 1970 masterpiece ‘The Conformist’ (Il conformista), based on Alberto Moravia’s 1951 novel of the same name.
In that I dare suggest further viewing of Bertolucci’s 1971 classic ‘Novecento’ (1900), in which (from recall, I am not allowed to be “in possession”) at something over an hour into Part 1, the loft scene in which Olmo and Alfredo ‘get to know each other’ is graphic and in full colour.
The lesson is for people to mind their own affair finally, go about their own business, take care they are not judged themselves, and found wanting.

Gil Hardwick

I was going to add, concerning dogs, the new generation of our family – boys and girlfriends alike – keep pets (all since desexed for other reasons) which lie on the lounge and leg up, head down, as their expression goes, “put on their lipstick.”
No point chastising them, the dog will adopt the silliest grin and wag its tail happily.

peterhoo

Gil, you offer a very tidy explanation about how in Western law one connects the action and the mind behind the act. You are right in how you explain this.
Recently I attended a public debate in Wellington, New Zealand. Victims and survivors of crimes committed by those judged to be insane want this link between actus reus and men rea broken. In court cases these victims and survivors are involved in, current outcomes are viewed by them as unjust – they want the insane person to have a public and legal profile of guilt. To hear a judge utter the words “not guilty” where a person judged to be insane and has brought about their pain is considered unpalatable. What they seek in New Zealand law is a new legal verdict of “guilty, but insane”.
While I listened empathetically to that was being argued for, I want to keep the linking of “the guilty act itself (actus reus) and the guilty mind behind the act (men rea)” inside how the law judges the accused. I don’t want this lobby group of victims and survivors to succeed.
For many years now I have argued for the preference of a concern for ethics over a concern for morality, a point one can see inside Tom’s article. I am ethically concerned about the morality of victimology. Being offended, and yes there can indeed be real suffering, is not in my mind the sole determiner of how a situation should be assessed.
Thanks Gil for your explanation of how the law links action to the mind behind the act.

Gil Hardwick

They are angling for incarceration at the governor’s pleasure, Peter, that’s the long and the short of their legal submission.
What you might find far more interesting is the simple fact that courts are now rarely admitting such arguments, for good reason.
You will be aware that a bit over three weeks ago we overwhelmingly voted in a new government in Canberra, for the same good reason.

16
0
Would love your thoughts, please comment.x
()
x
Scroll to Top